By Ronalyn R.
Tagudin
Doctor of
Philosophy Major in Development Management Student
ABSTRACT
The needs of the many outweigh the needs of
the few or, the one. Act always so as to promote the greatest good for the
greatest number of persons - utilitarianism.
The
moral rightness or wrongness of an action is to be judged by its results or
consequences. Consequences of an act determine its value. If an act produces
happiness of the people on a large scale, it is morally right; if it produces
unhappiness on a large scale, it is said to be morally wrong. However, the
result of an act may be actual or probable. An act may produce immediate
pleasure or happiness or it may produce happiness in remote future. So the act
that produces happiness in general is considered as morally right.
If the principle of utility be a
right principle to be governed by, and that in all cases, it follows from what
has been just observed, that whatever principle differs from it in any case
must necessarily be a wrong one. To prove any other principle, therefore, to be
a wrong one, there needs no more than just to show it to be what it is, a
principle of which the dictates are in some point or other different from those
of the principle of utility: to state it is to confute it (Wiley, 2008).
Keywords: greatest
good, utility, happiness, greatest number of persons, moral
INTRODUCTION
According to Jeremy Bentham,
utilitarianism is right if it tends to promote happiness and wrong if it tends
to produce the reverse of the happiness – not just the happiness of the
performer of the action but also that of everyone affected by it (Duignan,
2019).
Utilitarianism
is an effort to provide an answer to the practical question “What ought a
person to do?” The answer is that a person ought to act so as to produce the
best consequences possible. So, given that thought, are we obligated to act to
promote overall wellbeing when that is incompatible with our own? Admitting
that people do sometimes act benevolently – with the overall good of humanity
in mind. The view that utility is the
measure of virtue.
The Classical Approach
If anything could be identified as
the fundamental motivation behind the development of Classical Utilitarianism
it would be the desire to see useless, corrupt laws and social practices
changed. Accomplishing this goal required a normative ethical theory employed
as a critical tool. What is the truth about what makes an action or a policy a
morally good one, or morally right? But developing the theory itself was also
influenced by strong views about what was wrong in their society. The
conviction that, for example, some laws are bad resulted in analysis of why
they were bad. And, for Jeremy Bentham, what made them bad was their lack of utility,
their tendency to lead to unhappiness and misery without any compensating
happiness. If a law or an action doesn’t do any good, then it is isn’t any good
(Driver, 2014).
In this view, actions are approved
when they are such as to promote happiness, or pleasure, and disapproved of
when they have a tendency to cause unhappiness, or pain. We should be actively
trying to promote overall happiness thus, promote the overall well-being when that
it is incompatible with one’s own.
The Principle of
Utility
According to Wiley (2008), there are
principles of utility that should be considered as follows: (a) The principle
of utility is the foundation of the present work: it will be proper therefore
at the outset to give an explicit and determinate account of what is meant by
it. By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or
disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it
appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose
interest is in question: or, what is the same thing in other words, to promote
or to oppose that happiness; (b) By utility is meant that property in any
object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or
happiness, or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness
to the party whose interest is considered: if that party be the community in
general, then the happiness of the community: if a particular individual, then
the happiness of that individual; (c) The interest of the community is one of
the most general expressions that can occur; (d) It is in vain to talk of the
interest of the community, without understanding what is the interest of the
individual and; (e) An action then may be said to be comfortable to the
principle of utility, or, for shortness sake, to utility, when the tendency it
has to augment the happiness of the community is greater than any it has to
diminish it.
Further, Jeremy Bentham (1843)
formulated a theory of ethics and jurisprudence which is remarkable for its
clarity and consistency. He began with the psychological generalization that
all actions are motivated by the desire for pleasure and the fear of pain.
Hence he claimed,
“Nature
has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and
pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do as well as to
determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong, on
the other hand the chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their throne.
They govern us in all we do, in all we say, in all we think...”
Therefore, by the principle of
utility, Bentham maintains that the ideal method for determining whether an
individual’s action or a legal act is right or wrong would be through
evaluation of its total tendency to promote happiness or to promote unhappiness
to the other. In such a situation if the former predominates then the action is
right, if the latter then it is wrong.
However, Rasdall (1907) said that “…again
one’s own interest is taken into account in doing good to others. For it is
hoped that the others also will do good to one in return. An individual lives in
a society. As he is not self-sufficient, needs the assistance of others. An
enlightened self-interest is manifested in the cooperative spirit among the
individuals which is in order to secure their own interest.” In this regards,
Bentham claimed that benevolent actions are rewarded with pleasure as:
The
pleasures of benevolence are the pleasures resulting from the view of any pleasures
supposed to be possessed by the beings that may be the objects of benevolence…there
may also be called the pleasures of good will, the pleasures of sympathy, or
the pleasures of the benevolent or social affections.
Bentham thought that if doing well
to others makes the agent happy, then there can be no real opposition between
self-interest and the principle of utility; to promote the public happiness is
the way to make happy oneself.
Self-Sacrifice
Only while the world is in a very
imperfect state can it happen that anyone’s best chance of serving the
happiness of others is through the absolute sacrifice of his own happiness; but
while the world is in that imperfect state, I fully admit that the readiness to
make such a sacrifice is the highest virtue that can be found in man.
The utilitarian morality does
recognize that human beings can sacrifice their own greatest good for the good
of others; it merely refuses to admit that the sacrifice is itself a good. It
regards as wasted any sacrifice that doesn’t increase, or tend to increase, the
sum total of happiness. The only self-renunciation that it applauds is devotion
to the happiness, or to some of the means to happiness, of others. . . .
(Bennett, 2017).
Moreover, Bennett (2017) states that
as the practical way to get as close as possible to this ideal, the ethics of
utility would command two things. (1) First, laws and social
arrangements should place the happiness (or what for practical purposes we may
call the interest) of every individual as much as possible in harmony with the
interest of the whole. (2) Second,
education and opinion, which have such a vast power over human
character, should use that power to establish in the mind of every individual
an unbreakable link between his own happiness and the good of the whole;
especially between his own happiness and the kinds of conduct (whether doing or
allowing) that are conducive to universal happiness.
If it is done properly, it will tend to have two results: (a)
The individual won’t be able to conceive the possibility of being
personally happy while acting in ways opposed to the general good and; (b) In
each individual a direct impulse to promote the general good will be one of the
habitual motives of action, and the feelings connected with it will fill a
large and prominent place in his sentient existence. This is the true character
of the utilitarian morality.
Common Criticisms of
Utilitarianism
Again, to repeat something that the
opponents of utilitarianism are seldom fair enough to admit, namely that the
happiness that forms the utilitarian standard of what is right in conduct is
not the agent’s own happiness but that of all concerned. As between his own
happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly
impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator.
By far and away the most common criticism of
utilitarianism can be reduced simply to: "I don't like it" or
"It doesn't suit my way of thinking". Producing the greatest
good for the greatest number is fine as long as you are not hurting someone you
really love in the process. This is the case when utilitarianism runs into problems
when sentiment is involved.
In addition, it is impossible and too
difficult to apply. The happiness cannot be quantified or measured,
that there is no way of calculating a trade-off between intensity and extent,
or intensity and probability, or comparing happiness to suffering. We cannot
calculate all the effects for all the individuals (either because of the large
number of individuals involved, and/or because of the uncertainty). The
principle of utility is, essentially, a description of what makes something
right or wrong - so in order for it to fail, someone must give an example of
something which is useful but obviously wrong. The principle does not imply
that we can calculate what is right or wrong - completely accurately, in
advance, or at all! It does not harm the principle of utility at all merely to
comment that it is difficult for us to work out what is right - it is merely a
lament against the human condition (https://www.utilitarian.org/criticisms.html).
CONCLUSION
The doctrine that the basis of
morals is utility, or the greatest happiness principle, holds that actions are
right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong in proportion as
they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.
The only proof capable
of being given that an object is visible is that people actually see it. The
only proof that a sound is audible is that people hear it; and similarly with
the other sources of our experience. If happiness, the end that the utilitarian
doctrine proposes to itself, were not acknowledged in theory and in practice to
be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was an end.
No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except
the fact that each person desires his own happiness, so far as he thinks it is
attainable. But this is a fact; so we have not only all the proof there could be for such a proposition, and
all the proof that could possibly be
demanded, that happiness is a good, that each person’s happiness is a good to
that person, and therefore that general happiness is a good to the aggregate of
all persons. Happiness has
made good its claim to be one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of
the criteria of morality (Bennett, 2017).
REFERENCES
Bentham,
J. (1843). An Introduction to the
Principles of Morals and Legislation.
Bennett, J. (2017). Utilitarianism.
Driver,
J. (2014). The History of Utilitarianism.
Duignan,
B. & West, H. (2019). Utilitarianism Philosophy. http://www.britannica.com/topic/utilitarianism-philosophy/Historical-survey.
Retrieved, January 11, 2020.
Most
Common Criticisms of Utilitarianism.
Retrieved, from https://www.utilitarian.org/criticisms.html January 11, 2020.
Rasdall,
H. (1907). the Theory of Good and
Evil, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wiley,
J & Sons. (2008). Utilitarianism and on liberty: Including Mill’s’ Essay on
Bentham and selections from the writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin.
cdn.viglink.com/api/vglnk.js
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteAs stated by Stanford Medical, It's indeed the one and ONLY reason women in this country get to live 10 years more and weigh 19 kilos less than we do.
ReplyDelete(Just so you know, it has absoloutely NOTHING to do with genetics or some secret exercise and absolutely EVERYTHING to "how" they eat.)
P.S, What I said is "HOW", not "what"...
Click this link to find out if this little questionnaire can help you discover your true weight loss possibility