Popular Posts

Tuesday, October 14, 2025

Jean -Jacques Rousseau and the general will

 Jennifer C. Bungubung

 Divine World College of Laoag


Abstract 

Jean-Jacques Rousseau's concept of the General Will explores the relationship between individual freedom and collective power. This paper looks at Rousseau's vision of a society guided by the General Will. It explores how this concept aims to strike a balance between individual freedom and the community's needs. The paper also investigates how to define and enforce the General Will. It discusses the potential for it to act as a unifying force, along with the risk of it becoming a tool for oppression. By examining the tensions in Rousseau's theory, this paper offers a critical view of its lasting relevance in today's conversations about Democracy, legitimacy, and political authority.

Keywords: General Will, Common Good, Personal Interest. Lawgiver, Citizen, Collective responsibility, Democracy

Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778)

Jean-Jacques Rousseau was a Swiss-born philosopher, writer, and political theorist whose treatises and novels inspired the leaders of the French Revolution and the Romantic generation (Cranston, M., and Duignan, B., 2025). He was born to Isaac Rousseau and Suzanne Bernard in Geneva on June 28, 1712. His mother died only a few days later, on July 7, and his only sibling, an older brother, ran away from home when Rousseau was still a child. Rousseau was therefore brought up mainly by his father, a clockmaker, with whom he read ancient Greek and Roman literature, such as the Lives of Plutarch, at an early age. His father got into a quarrel with a French captain and, at the risk of imprisonment, left Geneva for the rest of his life. Rousseau stayed behind and was cared for by an uncle, who sent him and his cousin to study in the village of Bosey. In 1725, Rousseau was apprenticed to an engraver and began to learn the trade. Although he did not detest the work, he thought his master to be violent and tyrannical. He therefore left Geneva in 1728 and fled to Annecy. Here he met Louise de Warens, who was instrumental in his conversion to Catholicism, which forced him to forfeit his Genevan citizenship (in 1754, he would make a return to Geneva and publicly convert back to Calvinism). Rousseau's relationship with Mme. de Warens lasted for several years and eventually became romantic. During this time, he earned money through secretarial, teaching, and musical jobs. (Fieser and Dowden, 1995)

Jean-Jacques Rousseau remains an essential figure in the history of philosophy, both because of his contributions to political philosophy and moral psychology and on account of his influence on later thinkers. Rousseau's own view of most philosophy and philosophers was firmly negative, seeing them as post-hoc rationalizers of self-interest, as apologists for various forms of tyranny, and as playing a role in the alienation of the modern individual from humanity's natural impulse to compassion. The concern that dominates Rousseau's work is to find a way of preserving human freedom in a world where people are increasingly dependent on one another to satisfy their needs. This concern has two dimensions: material and psychological, with the latter being more important. In the modern world, human beings derive their sense of identity and value from the opinions of others, which Rousseau sees as corrosive of freedom and destructive of individual authenticity. In his mature work, he principally explores two routes to achieving and protecting freedom: the first is a political one aimed at constructing institutions that permit and foster the coexistence of free and equal citizens in a community where they themselves are sovereign; the second is a project for child development and education that nurtures autonomy and avoids the genesis of the most destructive forms of self-interest. However, although Rousseau believes that the coexistence of human beings in relations of equality and freedom is possible, he is consistently and overwhelmingly pessimistic that humanity will escape a dystopia of alienation, oppression, and unfreedom. In addition to his contributions to philosophy, Rousseau was active as a composer, a music theorist, a pioneer of modern autobiography, a novelist, and a botanist. Rousseau's appreciation of the wonders of nature and his emphasis on the importance of feeling and emotion made him a significant influence on and anticipator of the romantic movement. To a considerable extent, the interests and concerns that mark his philosophical work also inform these other activities, and Rousseau's contributions in ostensibly non-philosophical fields often serve to illuminate his philosophical commitments and arguments. (Malpas, 2012)

Rousseau’s contributions to political philosophy are scattered among various works, most notable of which are the Discourse on Inequality, the Discourse on Political EconomyThe Social Contract, and Considerations on the Government of Poland. However, many of his other works, both major and minor, contain passages that amplify or illuminate the political ideas in those works. His central doctrine in politics is that a state can be legitimate only if it is guided by the “general will” of its members. This idea finds its most detailed treatment in The Social Contract.

 

The Social Contract and the Birth of the General Will

 

            Rousseau starts The Social Contract with his famous statement: “Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains.” He believed that people are naturally good and free in their original state of nature, but they become corrupted by society and inequality. To regain freedom and create a fair political order, Rousseau proposed a new kind of social agreement, the social contract. In this contract, individuals agree together to form a community. This community is guided not by personal desires or private interests but by the general will, which represents the shared will of the people focused on the common good. By accepting this collective will, Rousseau argued, individuals do not lose their freedom. Instead, they find it in a higher form: the freedom of moral and civic autonomy.

Rousseau’s account of the general will contains unclear points that have sparked interest among commentators since its first publication. The central tension lies between a democratic view, where the general will is simply what citizens decide together in their sovereign assembly, and another interpretation where the general will represents the common interest of citizens, existing apart from what any individual actually wants (Bertram, 2012). Additionally, there is the perspective of the general will as the will of individual citizens directed toward the common good (Canon, 2022). Each of these interpretations finds some basis in Rousseau's writings and has had an impact. Modern ideas about Democracy often refer to Rousseau's discussion in Book 2, Chapter 3 of The Social Contract. These discussions typically start with Condorcet's jury theorem, viewing democratic processes as a way to discover the truth about the public interest. They then interpret the general will as a means of discussion aimed at outcomes that meet individual preferences and justify the authority of the state. The tension between the "democratic" and "transcendental" views can be lessened if we understand Rousseau to be suggesting that, under the right conditions and procedures, citizen legislators will tend to agree on laws that reflect their common interest. However, when those conditions and procedures are lacking, the state inherently lacks legitimacy. This interpretation leads to a view similar to a posteriori philosophical anarchism. This view suggests that while it is theoretically possible for a state to have legitimate authority over its citizens, all actual states—and especially those we encounter in the modern world—are likely to fail in meeting the criteria for legitimacy.

Rousseau argues that for the general will to be truly general, it must come from everyone and apply to everyone. This idea has both critical and formal aspects. Formally, Rousseau states that the law must be general in application and universal in scope. The law cannot name specific individuals, and it must apply to all people within the state. Rousseau believes that this condition will lead citizens, even when considering their own private interests, to support laws that protect the common interest fairly and that are not overly burdensome or intrusive. However, for this to happen, citizens' situations must be broadly similar to one another. In a state with diverse lifestyles and occupations, significant cultural diversity, or high economic inequality, the impact of the laws will not be the same for everyone. In these cases, a citizen may struggle to view the general will by only imagining how general and universal laws affect their own situation. (Rousseau, 2010)

 

Understanding the General Will

 

 The general will represent what is best for the whole community. In contrast, the will of all adds up to individual preferences. The general will aim for the common good and go beyond personal or group interests. It is not just based on majority opinion; it comes from the collective reasoning of citizens who prioritise the community's welfare over their own self-interest. Rousseau's idea questions the belief that freedom means doing whatever one pleases. For him, true freedom is following a law that one creates for oneself. This law reflects the general will. As a result, individuals become both the authors and subjects of the rules they follow, ensuring equality and legitimacy in governance.

For Rousseau, however, the general will is not an abstract ideal. It is instead the will actually held by the people in their capacity as citizens. Rousseau’s conception is thus political and differs from the more universal conception of the general will held by Diderot. To partake in the general will means, for Rousseau, to reflect upon and to vote based on one's sense of justice. Individuals become conscious of their interests as citizens, according to Rousseau, and thus of the interest of the republic as a whole, not through spirited discussions but, on the contrary, by following their personal conscience in the "silence of the passions." In this sense, the public assembly does not debate so much as disclose the general will of the people. Rousseau argued that the general will is intrinsically right, but he also criticised in some works (mainly in his Discours sur les sciences et les arts (1750; Discourse on the Sciences and Arts) the rationalist elevation of reason above feelings. This has provoked scholarly debate about the rational and affective dimensions of the general will. On the one hand, the general will reflects the rational interest of the individual (as a citizen) as well as that of the people as a whole. On the other hand, the general will not be purely rational because it emerges out of an attachment and even a love for one's political community. (Munro, 2013)

 

The Function of the Lawgiver and the Citizen

 

Rousseau placed a strong emphasis on citizens' active involvement in forming the general will. Active citizens who act out of civic virtue and prioritise the common good over their own interests are necessary for a decent society. Additionally, he developed the concept of the Lawgiver, a wise founder who assists the populace in determining the collective will and creating rules that serve the common welfare. However, the people themselves always retain sovereignty once the laws are put in place.

In Rousseau’s The Social Contract, the roles of the Lawgiver and the Citizen are key to understanding how the General Will works within a political community. Each has a distinct but connected role in shaping and maintaining a fair and stable society. In fact, the Lawgiver has both "a task which is beyond human powers and a non-existent authority for its execution." And they must also speak to the people in terms they can understand, for it takes good government to create "the social spirit" that makes people understand, appreciate, and perpetuate good government (Rousseau, 2020)

The Lawgiver holds a unique, almost sacred place in Rousseau’s political theory. He is not a ruler or magistrate but a visionary founder who helps create the fundamental laws and institutions that express the General Will. The Lawgiver’s job is to turn the people’s collective wishes for the common good into a clear set of laws. However, the Lawgiver does not impose his own will; instead, he helps the people see their true interests and form a moral and political community. Rousseau likens the Lawgiver to an architect who builds the foundation on which the state can last.

On the other hand, the Citizen represents the active member of the sovereign body. For Rousseau, citizens are both the creators and subjects of the laws—they make the laws as part of the collective sovereign and follow them as individuals. This dual role captures Rousseau’s principle of freedom: by obeying laws they have made for themselves, citizens are not controlled by others but governed by their own shared will.

 The harmony between the Lawgiver and the Citizen ensures that the General Will shows the true interests of everyone. The Lawgiver establishes the moral and institutional framework, while the citizens support it through their engagement and commitment to the common good. When both fulfill their roles, society achieves legitimacy, equality, and moral unity—these are the ideals central to Rousseau’s vision of political life.

 

Remarks and Impact

 

Rousseau's general will theory has come under attack for being idealistic and even dangerous if misinterpreted. Others have argued that it could be used to justify authoritarian rule in the name of the "common good." However, Rousseau intended to promote equality and collective freedom, not tyranny. He aimed to create a moral society where all members share the responsibility for the principles and rules that shape them.

Despite these debates, Rousseau's impact remains strong. His demand for moral and civic equality still resonates in modern talks about Democracy, social justice, and participatory governance. The General Will serves as a potent reminder that political legitimacy should always be based on the common good of the community, not the interests of a select group.

 

Conclusion

Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s idea of the general will is one of the most impactful and thought-provoking concepts in political philosophy. It pushes societies to balance individual freedom with collective responsibility and personal interest with the common good. In Rousseau’s ideal republic, true liberty is found not in isolation but in unity. This occurs when citizens willingly choose to pursue together what benefits everyone.

His concept of the General Will is essential to modern political thought. In The Social Contract, Rousseau envisioned a society where absolute authority comes from the agreement of free and equal citizens, not from power or privilege. The General Will stands for the moral and common good that unites individuals into a single political community. Rousseau's ideas challenged the traditional foundations of government and inspired democratic movements that sought to empower the people. He believed that true freedom is found in obeying laws that one imposes on oneself, a concept that transformed the understanding of citizenship and responsibility within the state.

Despite facing criticism and various interpretations, Rousseau's ideas continue to matter today. In an era still grappling with inequality, social division, and political corruption, his plea for participation, moral unity, and commitment to the common good is crucial. His philosophy reminds us that Democracy is more than just a form of government; it is a shared commitment to justice and the well-being of all.

Ultimately, Rousseau’s vision of the General Will encourages societies to balance individual freedom with collective responsibility. This remains a timeless goal for peaceful human coexistence.

REFERENCES:

Bertram, C. (2012). Rousseau's Legacy in Two Conceptions of the General Will: Democratic and Transcendent

Canon. S. (2022). Three General Wills in Rousseau, The Review of Politics

Carnston, M. & Duignan, B. (2025). Literature, Novels & Short Stories. Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/biography/Jean-Jacques-Rousseau

Fieser, J, and Dowden, B. (1995). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from https://iep.utm.edu/rousseau

Malpas, J. (2012). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 

Munro, A. (2013). Politics, Law, and Government

Rousseau, J. (2010). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

 

Rousseau, J. (2020). The Social Contract Book 2, Chapter 7: The Lawgiver Summary.  https://boatcontinuing.com/q9h97sj5?key=23b279e99ed6a529a30f577cdce2aeb9

https://boatcontinuing.com/q9h97sj5?key=23b279e99ed6a529a30f577cdce2aeb9

No comments:

Post a Comment

Jean -Jacques Rousseau and the general will

  Jennifer C. Bungubung  Divine World College of Laoag Abstract  Jean-Jacques Rousseau's concept of the General Will explores the rela...